Difference between revisions of "Diversity In Libertarianism"

From Critiques Of Libertarianism
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 5: Line 5:
  
 
It would be nice if there was a simple dismissal of libertarianism, but there are so many different kinds that no one argument could apply.
 
It would be nice if there was a simple dismissal of libertarianism, but there are so many different kinds that no one argument could apply.
 +
 +
metaphysical (the original use) versus political
 +
normative (versus positive) theoryleft and right
 +
    4 types in "Utopia"
 +
    rationalist vs. antirationalist
 +
    essentialist vs. pragmatist libertarians
 +
        http://www.davidbrin.com/libertarianarticle2.html
 +
    "Justice For The Here And Now", Sterba
 +
        distinguishes Spencerian and Lockean libertarians, based on primacy of
 +
        liberty or rights.  Shows how either results in requirement for basic
 +
        positive rights.
 +
        Rebuts Machan, Rasmussen, Hospers, Mack, and Narvesson.
 +
    Basis of desires versus liberty.
 +
        "Both Hayek and Rothbard maintain that, in societies like
 +
        theirs, the desirable always concords with liberty (or maximal
 +
        liberty). Rothbard achieved this concordance by molding his
 +
        sensibilities about the desirable to fit his definition of
 +
        liberty. Hayek achieved this concordance by molding his
 +
        definition of liberty to fit his sensibilities about the
 +
        desirable.
 +
        http://www.vaz1.net/bill/anarchism/library/MereLibertarianism.html
 +
    D Friedman hardcore vs soft core
 +
        ideologues versus preferences (gut)
 +
        http://daviddfriedman.blogspot.com/2008/08/two-paths-for-libertarian-party.html
 +
    Right, left, and other
 +
        http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/libertarianism/
 +
        Radical right libertarians -- such as Rothbard (1978, 1982) and Kirzner (1978)
 +
        Lockean right-libertarians -- such as Nozick (1974)
 +
        Georgist libertarianism -- as developed, for example, by George (1879, 1892) and Steiner (1977, 1980, 1981, 1994)
 +
        ethical libertarianism
 +
        political libertarianism
 +
        philosophical libertarianism (free will)
 +
        left/right/socialist (Karl Widerquist's encyclopedia article)
 +
    value vs right (Narvesson)
 +
        http://www.againstpolitics.com/libertarianism/
 +
        (1) that liberty is the sole value to be promoted by governments and
 +
        individuals (sometimes called the "teleological" version of
 +
        libertarianism) and
 +
        (2) that liberty is our sole right (sometimes called "deontological"
 +
        libertarianism; this is the view that the word "libertarianism",
 +
        unqualified, is generally taken to stand for nowadays.)
 +
    "the right" versus "the good"?
 +
    rights theory, consequentialist, human flourishing
 +
        http://volokh.com/archives/archive_2004_07_28.shtml#1091184329
 +
    Primary division of libertarians:
 +
        consequentialists (Hume, Hayek, Epstein, Rand)
 +
        natural rights (Nozick, etc.)
 +
        see http://www.reason.com/9903/bk.ls.fuzzy.html
 +
    LP vs non-LP
 +
    LP vs LP reform
 +
    Austrian vs. Chicago economics
 +
    Rawlsekians
 +
        http://www.amconmag.com/article/2008/jul/28/00024//
 +
        Rawls' liberty principle appeals to the so-called Rawlsekians, a group
 +
 +
        http://www.amconmag.com/article/2008/jul/28/00024//
 +
        Rawls' liberty principle appeals to the so-called Rawlsekians, a group
 +
        of young libertarians who want to combine the views of Rawls with those
 +
        of Friedrich Hayek, but Rawls himself was no Hayekian.
 +
    So you can see, libertarianism can attract two types of people:
 +
        1- Those that are libertarian because they agree with the libertarian means of minimal government.
 +
        2- Those that are libertarian because they believe that libertarian means will produce the end result that they desire.
 +
        http://www.dailykos.com/story/2007/2/27/15718/5328
 +
 +
Samuel Freeman does a good job of showing how libertarian ideas of property differ
 +
from liberal ideas in his "Illiberal Libertarians: Why Libertarianism Is Not a
 +
Liberal View" paper, Philosophy & Public
 +
Affairs, Vol. 30 n. 2. Locke is neither libertarian nor liberal on property
 +
on this account, and I think that's the right interpretation.)
 +
Classification of liberals.
 +
        Having no conception of a political society, libertarians have no
 +
        conception of the common good, those basic interests of each individual
 +
        that according to liberals are to be maintained for the sake of justice
 +
        by the impartial exercise of public political power. (page 149;
 +
        footnote omitted)
 +
        "that libertarianism's resemblance to liberalism is superficial; in the
 +
        end, libertarians reject essential liberal institutions. Correctly
 +
        understood, libertarianism resembles a view that liberalism historically
 +
        defined itself against, the doctrine of private political power that
 +
        underlies feudalism. Like feudalism, libertarianism conceives of
 +
        justified political power as based in a network of private contracts.
 +
        It rejects the idea, essential to liberalism, that political power is
 +
        a public power, to be impartially exercised for the common good."
 +
1 classical liberals:  laissez fair, but allows redistribution to preserve mkts
 +
        allow's property-owner's state (p123)
 +
2 high liberals:        philosophical liberalism and institutions
 +
3 libertarians
 +
Locke's Second Treatise par. 73, 120, 138, 139 show government has authority to
 +
regulate, tax, and burden property for the common good.
 +
Liberalism (classical or high) has 6 institutional features (p123):
 +
        1. the public recognition and legal enforcement of basic rights and
 +
          liberties equally provided for all citizens
 +
        2. some account of equality of opportunity with open careers and
 +
          positions
 +
        3. a central role assigned to efficient markets in allocating
 +
          productive resources
 +
        4. government's role in the production of public goods
 +
        5. government's duty to provide a social minimum
 +
        6. the public nature of political authority
 +
 +
"the right" versus "the good".
 +
"The right" in this sense is what Robyn Eckersley defines as "the idea that
 +
the common structure of political action should constrain and limit what
 +
elected governments may decide in the name of the state, what citizens may do
 +
in pursuit of their own conceptions of the good life and what economic actors
 +
may do in pursuit of economic gain."

Revision as of 21:54, 23 August 2010