Difference between revisions of "Fallacies Of Philosophy"

From Critiques Of Libertarianism
Jump to: navigation, search
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
[[Category:Libertarian Philosophy]]
+
[[Category:Fallacies|200]]
 
{{DES | des = A great deal of philosophy is grossly misleading from the very start.}}
 
{{DES | des = A great deal of philosophy is grossly misleading from the very start.}}
  
Line 9: Line 9:
  
 
"Philosophy, take it by and large, has in fact been simply the anthropocentrism of the educated and intelligent, as religion is the anthropocentrism of the others." David Stove
 
"Philosophy, take it by and large, has in fact been simply the anthropocentrism of the educated and intelligent, as religion is the anthropocentrism of the others." David Stove
 +
 +
=== Philosophers frequently rely on illogic. ===
 +
 +
The most famous is [[David Hume]]'s identification of the "is-ought problem".  Philosophers routinely start with a statement of what "is", but then somehow illogically leap to what "ought".  For a large list of 40 problematic examples, see "[http://web.maths.unsw.edu.au/~jim/wrongthoughts.html What is Wrong with Our Thoughts? A Neo-Positivist Credo]".
  
 
=== Assumptions that do not match reality. ===
 
=== Assumptions that do not match reality. ===
Line 15: Line 19:
 
Often these assumptions are disguised as "apriori knowledge".  Belief in a priori knowledge is touchingly naive. It is a philosophical superstition, just as souls are.
 
Often these assumptions are disguised as "apriori knowledge".  Belief in a priori knowledge is touchingly naive. It is a philosophical superstition, just as souls are.
  
Science has a superior approach, modeling.  You don't "believe" in models. You accept or reject them based on whether they are accurate enough to beat out other models. Certainty is hardly an objective of science. Science is heuristic, not certain.
+
Science has a superior approach, modeling.  You don't "believe" in models. You accept or reject them based on whether they are accurate enough to beat out other models. Certainty is hardly an objective of science. Science is heuristic, not certain.  And science documents where its assumptions and models fail.
 +
 
 +
See [[Existential Comics 259: A Dialogue on Freedom]] for an example from [[Robert Nozick]].
 +
 
 +
=== Calvinball ===
 +
Moral philosophy is [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Calvin_and_Hobbes#Calvinball Calvinball].  Rules are made up as you go.  Assumptions are added as needed to get the desired results.  Every conclusion can be reversed by the addition of a sufficiently potent assumption.  The fancy name for this is defeasible argument.  The result is that moral philosophy is a post-hoc intellectual excuse for previously chosen positions.  It can also serve as a quick introduction of where selected assumptions can lead, with the caveat that with minor tweaks the entirely opposite results can hold.
 +
 
 +
=== Reifications ===
 +
The fallacy of treating an abstraction as if it were a real thing.  Ideas such as "[[Inviolable Private Sphere of Rights]]" abound: indeed innumerable non-legal (moral) ideas of rights undergo reification.
 +
 
 +
=== Naive Folk Models ===
 +
Many philosophical conundrums arise because of naive folk models which we know are not true.  Ideas such as objects and identity are convenient labels that for some purposes suffice but are reifications.  Boundaries cannot be clearly defined and time changes everything.  I am not the same as I was a minute ago: it is merely a convenient folk model to treat me so.  See [[A Is A]] for some examples.
 +
 
 +
=== Incomplete Statements ===
 +
Much philosophy is rooted in incomplete statements.  For example, "Man was meant to live free."  (Foundation for Economic Education calls this "the freedom philosophy.")  But meant BY WHOM?  Such a statement is nonsensical because it is lacking a necessary subject or object: it properly should be written "X meant man to live free", where X is "nature" or "god" or whatever reification (fiction) is needed for the argument.  It's funny that with the libertarian emphasis on primacy of values of individuals, which they use to rebut claims about social values that some libertarians resort to such evasive claims.  It's obvious that most individuals hold different values: "I should live free, everybody else should be regulated for my benefit."  And free of what?
 +
 
 +
Almost all uses by libertarians of "[[A Positive Model Of Rights|rights]]", "desert", "[[What Is Liberty?|freedom]]", "ought", "justified" and other important philosophical terms suffer from this problem.
 +
 
 +
Incomplete statements are generally read as implying a universal, but they are usually ambiguous.
  
 
=== Philosophers are very poor at second-best solutions. ===
 
=== Philosophers are very poor at second-best solutions. ===
Line 25: Line 47:
 
They are usually prescientific.  David Hume wrote:  
 
They are usually prescientific.  David Hume wrote:  
 
{{QuoteOne | Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding/flames}}
 
{{QuoteOne | Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding/flames}}
When confronted with real-world problems that could have multiple causes, logical verbal models are insufficient. You MUST introduce measurement and mathematics into your models if you want to have any hope of valid answers. Logical verbal models are sufficient to specify possible chains (or networks) of causation, but telling which are significant is a quantitative problem that requires measurement.  See: [[The Parable Of The Ship]].
+
When confronted with real-world problems that could have multiple causes, logical verbal models are insufficient. You MUST introduce measurement and mathematics into your models if you want to have any hope of valid answers. Logical verbal models are sufficient to specify possible chains (or networks) of causation, but telling which are significant is a quantitative problem that requires measurement.  See: [[Parable of the ship: why Austrian Economics fails.|The Parable Of The Ship]].
  
 
Economics has a branch called econometrics which is concerned with providing empirical content.  Philosophy usually lacks such content, and is usually backed with gut feelings and blustering authority.  Better alternatives would be roots in scientific aspects of psychology, anthropology, evolution, and other fields.
 
Economics has a branch called econometrics which is concerned with providing empirical content.  Philosophy usually lacks such content, and is usually backed with gut feelings and blustering authority.  Better alternatives would be roots in scientific aspects of psychology, anthropology, evolution, and other fields.
Line 43: Line 65:
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
[http://delong.typepad.com/sdj/2011/02/delong-smackdown-watch-lexicographic-preferences.html Brad DeLong]
 
[http://delong.typepad.com/sdj/2011/02/delong-smackdown-watch-lexicographic-preferences.html Brad DeLong]
 +
 +
=== Assuming that small cases will scale up. ===
 +
Engineers know that any time you scale up something, you can reach a point where it no longer works.  Something that works between a pair of people might not work for a trio, for example.
 +
 +
=== Claiming that math is an example of objective truth ===
 +
I frequently see thing such as:
 +
 +
"2+2=4 is true whether or not you or I believe it. It's objectively true."
 +
 +
Wow, that is horseshit. 2+2=4 is one statement out of an infinitude which also includes 2+2=1. Neither statement is "true" in most senses of truth (please tell me which one you mean!) Both are abstract models that may or may not correspond to real world examples. For example, 2 water drops plus 2 water drops could equal one big water drop. And I highly recommend [https://www.gutenberg.org/files/2004/2004-h/2004-h.htm Pigs is Pigs] for a famous example of 1+1=thousands. In math, 2 infinities (aleph null) plus two infinities still equals one infinity. So mathematicians have counterexamples for your "objective truth". But there is also another facet of math you probably don't know. Math involves selection of statements based on their "beauty" (ie. desires of mathematicians.) Mathematicians usually prefer 2+2=4 because they find arithmetic beautiful: it is far more often superior for modelling than 2+2=1 usually is. In the development of calculus, philosophers complained greatly about infinitesimals and other concepts, but mathematicians found it beautiful anyway.
 +
 +
Nor are humans capable of objectivity or recognizing an objective truth. The best we have is intersubjective corroboration.
 +
 +
Another caveat: I don't know where people get the philosophical idea that math is objectively true.  I haven't seen it attributed.
  
 
=== Presuming that clear and sharp categories can be used as a starting point. ===
 
=== Presuming that clear and sharp categories can be used as a starting point. ===
Line 66: Line 102:
 
That's how I view most philosophical ideas such as truth, justice, good, evil, etc.  While you can study the relationships between such ideas endlessly, as you can the relationships between the Chinese categories, you do not have much hope of getting to the root explanations, as we have in biology, because the unifying basis is not obvious in these far descended ideas.  Starting with such ideas is a pretty clear [[wikipedia:Skyhook_(concept)#Skyhooks_and_cranes|skyhook]].  These ideas need to be explained from much simpler, preferably positivist ideas rooted in evolution, anthropology, game theory, etc.
 
That's how I view most philosophical ideas such as truth, justice, good, evil, etc.  While you can study the relationships between such ideas endlessly, as you can the relationships between the Chinese categories, you do not have much hope of getting to the root explanations, as we have in biology, because the unifying basis is not obvious in these far descended ideas.  Starting with such ideas is a pretty clear [[wikipedia:Skyhook_(concept)#Skyhooks_and_cranes|skyhook]].  These ideas need to be explained from much simpler, preferably positivist ideas rooted in evolution, anthropology, game theory, etc.
  
The science of cladistics bases classifications on shared, derived characteristics.  Philosophers
+
The science of cladistics bases classifications on shared, derived characteristics.  Philosophers seldom even get to a simple Venn Diagram.
 +
 
 +
=== Glittering Generalities Of Propaganda ===
 +
 
 +
Very often, a philosophical statement omits qualifiers.  This has the horrible effect of permitting interpretation as stating a universal.  We are often expected to accept such universals because of some specific evidence, but that begs the problem of induction.  This is a widely used principle of propaganda, the glittering generality.
 +
 
 +
"Free To Choose"
 +
* Who?
 +
* Is how free?
 +
* To choose what kinds of things?
 +
* From what limited set of choices?
 +
* Under what conditions?
 +
 
 +
"I have a right."
 +
* To what?
 +
* For what purpose?
 +
* Limited by?
 +
* A right against whom?
 +
* At what costs to others?
 +
* Claimed by?
 +
* Known because?
 +
* Created by?
 +
* Enforced by?
  
=== Fallacy of hidden assumption of an object. ===
+
<!-- DPL has problems with categories that have a single quote in themUse these explicit workarounds. -->
"I have a right." Against whom? (much more to put here.)
+
<!-- otherwise, we would use {{Links}} and {{Quotes}} -->
 +
{{List|title=Fallacies Of Philosophy|links=true}}
 +
{{Quotations|title=Fallacies Of Philosophy|quotes=true}}

Latest revision as of 16:29, 11 May 2020